Economics of Defense

views updated

Economics of Defense

BIBLIOGRAPHY

It is essential to see defense as an economic problem and to understand what economizing means. It is also important for nations to attempt to use an economic calculus (quantitative economic analysis) in making choices and to shape the institutional arrangements in defense planning with care. Although the setting for defense planning varies from nation to nation, these issues are similar everywhere.

The economic problem. Choosing among possible defense activities can be viewed as an economic problem: that of allocating available resources so as to get the greatest good from them. The alternatives include various possible sizes of the defense budget, i.e., various allocations of resources to defense, other governmental functions, and the private sector. The alternatives then include various allocations of the total defense budget among particular “outputs,” or missions, such as nuclear retaliatory capability, limited-war capability, token forces, arms control, civil defense, various kinds of mobilization bases, sealift, and so on. As with outputs in the private sector, some of these are close to being final goods and some (like sealift) are intermediate outputs, which are used in turn to produce other outputs.

Choices among various ways of producing these outputs are sometimes called “lower-level” choices. Here are included such options as the use of alternative base locations, logistic arrangements, launch facilities, contract provisions, and personnel policies. In creating defense forces there are many substitution possibilities—larger regiments versus better-equipped regiments, electronic countermeasures versus numbers of missiles, truck transport versus airlift, rifles versus mortars. These lower-level choices are economic problems too. When one estimates the costs and gains of different submarine forces and deployments, one is concerned with the worth of resources in competing uses. When one considers alternative locations for air-defense missiles or sites for vehicle fuel storage and repairs, one is dealing with the worth of these resources in rival uses.

Needless to say, the choices at different levels are not independent of each other. The size of the budget should depend upon, among other things, the costs and gains of producing specific capabilities, i.e., the specific lower-level options that confront a nation. In turn, the choices at lower levels should often depend upon the size of the budget.

Another set of alternatives embraces various kinds of research and development intended to invent new defense policies or systems. Effective attempts to advance technology and efficient resource allocation within any given technology are both important; the absence of either would leave defense or any other activity at a comparatively primitive stage. Because relatively great uncertainties surround research and development alternatives, choosing among them calls for a different approach from decision making under conditions of comparative certainty (Klein & Meckling 1958; Nelson 1961).

Economizing. “Economizing” does not imply scrimping and penny-pinching in defense (or in any other activity), nor does it call for meeting all needs. Instead, in defense planning “economizing” implies cutting defense costs whenever resources can produce more-valuable outputs elsewhere and meeting defense needs whenever they are more important than other needs.

Many persons believe in or talk as if they believe in “needs” or “requirements” that should be met regardless of cost. Others seem to believe in cost or budget ceilings that must be adhered to no matter how large the gains that might be obtained by going above the ceiling. Still others believe that one should set up priority lists like the following: (1) laser; (2) new supersonic bomber; (3) improved long-range camera. What such a list means is hard to see: should all resources go to the first item? should resources go to the first item until an extra dollar there brings a zero return, even though the other items are worth something? should more money be spent on the first item than on the second and more on the second than on the third? The trouble is that a priority list does not face the real question: how much should be allocated to each item?

None of these beliefs give proper guidance. Hard though it may be to apply, the economic principle is the one to keep in mind: make any resource shift that yields more than it costs. When gain exceeds costs, a transfer of resources produces net gains and, thus, a greater total output. There are two major approaches to the application of this principle: improvement of the economic calculus (information about the costs and gains from alternative courses of action) and improvement of the institutional arrangements that shape defense choices. As in the private economy, both are important. Identification of the correct choice will not help much if institutions are such as to lead decision makers to make a different choice. On the other hand, better institutions are hard to devise if good choices cannot be identified. In making good decisions at every level—decisions about the size of budgets and about the allocation of given budgets—both the institutional arrangements and the economic calculus play an important role.

The possibility of an economic calculus. First of all, what does “economic efficiency” really mean? If one could calculate all gains and costs in commensurable terms, if these amounts were universally and unambiguously true, and if there were no uncertainties, the correct actions would be those that yielded net gains and they could be conclusively identified. In most activities, certainly in defense, these conditions do not hold. One major stumbling block is the fact that there is no generally accepted value that can be assigned to a change in the amount of defense as a whole or to an increment in any defense mission.

We can sometimes derive a production-possibility curve showing the various combinations of two defense outputs—say, ability to shoot down enemy missiles and ability to retaliate—attainable with the same total budget. But we have no indifference curves, and no price tags, to show how extra units of each capability should be valued. It is impossible, therefore, to identify the most valuable or optimal combination. (Even the most valuable combination would not necessarily be optimal, because there would be no assurance that the given budget was optimal.)

By exploring alternative ways of using the resources, however, one can sometimes show how to obtain more of one capability without sacrificing any of the other. Assuming there are no uncounted effects, such a change is an unambiguous improvement. In technical terminology, this constitutes moving to an efficient point on the production-possibility curve.

Moreover, when alternative actions affect only a single objective (seldom completely true), one can sometimes find a closely related type of improvement. By designing and comparing alternative ways to achieve that objective, one can often discover ways to achieve a specified amount of the objective at a lower cost or ways to achieve a larger amount of the objective at a specified cost. Such an improvement is akin to a shift toward an efficient point, because again the final result is the following: more of some desirable output can be produced without giving up anything else. This is the customary meaning of “economic efficiency.”

Program budgeting. One device that is intended to facilitate the use of an economic calculus in budgetary choices is program budgeting, which the U.S. Defense Department introduced in 1961. Its central feature is the presentation of costs for programs, or output categories (e.g., retaliatory capability, weapon systems, arms control), rather than for input categories (e.g., personnel, transportation). By thinking in terms of programs, officials can better take into account interdependencies— such as the effects of buying submarine-launched missiles or the worth of extra land-based ballistic missiles. Officials can presumably make better subjective judgments about the worth of output categories than they can make about the ultimate worth of inputs. These calculations also provide better clues to the worth of increments or decrements in output categories. Another feature of program budgeting is the presentation of the anticipated costs of a program decision for several years ahead rather than for one year at a time. This should help officials take into account the full-cost implications of decisions instead of merely the initial-payment implications.

Program budgeting is no panacea. Hard choices will still be relatively hard. There are difficulties, both conceptual and practical, in providing the most useful cost estimates. Also program budgeting, unless implemented with care, may be conducive to excessive centralization of authority, which itself entails disadvantages or costs. This will be considered below, in the discussion of the role of institutional arrangements. Our interest here is in program budgeting as an information system to facilitate economic calculations.

Cost-benefit analysis. Increasingly, nowadays, there are direct attempts to prepare an economic calculus to help one choose among alternatives. These alternatives are often called systems because —whether they are physically small guidance mechanisms or vast combinations of missiles, aircraft, bases, command-and-control arrangements, personnel, and procedures—they are sets of interrelated parts. Such cost-gain comparisons are sometimes called cost-effectiveness analyses or systems analyses, especially when they pertain to defense; operations research or operational analyses, particularly when they compare alternative modes of operation; cost—benefit analyses, originally where they evaluated natural-resource projects [seeWATER RESOURCES]; or simply economic analyses, where they examine conventional economic policies. The term “cost-benefit analyses” is now used rather widely, and it does seem to convey the underlying idea fairly well.

Cost-benefit analyses can be viewed as consisting of several elements: (1) the desired objectives, such as (in defense) being prepared to carry out specified missions; (2) the alternative systems, or means of trying to achieve the objectives; (3) the costs entailed by each of the systems; (4) models to help trace out the costs incurred and achievements provided; and (5) a criterion (involving both cost and achievement) to identify the best system. With regard to the last element, discussing the correct way to design criteria may seem like discussing the correct way to find the Holy Grail. In a world of uncertainty and nth best, judgments must help shape choices and no operational test of preferredness can be above suspicion. Moreover, analyses vary in their quality (which is hard to appraise) and in their applicability to different decisions. For these reasons the responsible decision makers must treat cost-benefit analyses as “consumer research” and introduce heroic judgments in reaching final decisions. In a sense, then, it may be both presumptuous and erroneous to discuss having a test of preferredness in these quantitative analyses.

Criteria should be discussed, nonetheless, in connection with such analysis. First, cost-benefit analysts must deal with a closely related set of issues: what are relevant impacts on achievement of objectives and what are relevant impacts on costs? (These issues confront one in the first four elements of cost-benefit analysis, of course, whether or not one includes a fifth element called criterion selection.) Second, cost-benefit analysts do apply criteria, especially in designing and redesigning the alternatives to be compared. They delete features that appear to be inefficient, add features that appear to be improvements, and probe for alternative combinations that are worth considering. This screening of possibilities and redesigning of alternative systems entails the use of criteria, and these should be explicitly considered and exhibited. Moreover, whether or not they ought to, analysts often present the final comparisons in terms of a criterion.

Thus, while it is wrong to talk as if a definitive criterion is an element of every analysis, we ought to emphasize certain points about criterion selection. First, many tests of preferredness can be quite misleading. For example, such tests as the ratio of gains to costs, the ratio of part of the gains to part of the costs, and the maximum gains for particular inputs should be avoided (Hitch & McKean 1960, pp. 158–181). Second, it should be stressed that good (although never perfect) criteria usually take one of the following forms: (1) maximum gains minus costs (to be used wherever possible); (2) maximum achievement of an objective for a given cost; or (3) minimum cost of achieving a specified amount of an objective.

Needless to say, analyses should attempt to take into account all gains and all costs. Some people feel that there are two types of gain or cost, economic and noneconomic, and that economic analysis has nothing to say about the latter. This distinction is neither very sound nor very useful. People pay for—that is, they value—paintings, as well as shoes; peace of mind, as well as aluminum pans; a lower probability of death, as well as garbage disposal. The significant categories are not economic and noneconomic items but (1) gains and costs that can be measured in monetary units, e.g., production or use of items, like steel, that have market prices to which users can adjust their transactions; (2) other commensurable effects, e.g., impacts on retaliatory capability of better warning systems as compared with the hardening of missile bases; (3) incommensurable effects that can be quantified separately but not in terms of a common unit, e.g., capability of destroying x targets and capability of showing resolve by putting y aircraft on forward bases; and (4) nonquantifiable effects. Examples of the latter are impacts on morale and thence on capability; impacts on the probability of limited war, of escalation, and of nuclear war; and impacts on the chances of working out mutually acceptable arms controls. In taking a position on an issue, each of us implicitly quantifies such considerations. But there is no way to make generally valid quantifications that would necessarily agree with those of other persons. These distinctions between types of effects of alternative policies do serve a useful purpose, however, especially in warning us of the limitations of cost-benefit analysis.

Cost-benefit analysis necessarily involves groping and the making of subjective judgments, not just briskly proceeding with dispassionate scientific measurements. No one says, “This is the defense objective, and here are the three alternative systems to be compared; now trace out the impacts of each on cost and on achievement of the objective, and indicate the preferred system.” What happens is that those making the analysis spend quite some time attempting an operational statement of an objective, for example, the capability, after receiving a specified strike, to destroy a designated set of targets with a stipulated probability. Then, a first attempt is made at designing the alternative ways of producing this capability. Preliminary costs are estimated. Members of the research team perceive that the alternative systems would affect other objectives, such as the deterring of minor aggressions or the providing of a flexible rather than a spasm response to major aggressions. Relations with other countries may be immediately involved. If the analysis is being made by a relatively small nation, for example, its defense posture would have subtle and crucial impacts on the reactions of neighboring countries and of large nations. The analysts redesign the alternatives in the light of these impacts, perhaps so that each alternative performs at least “acceptably” with respect to each objective. Next, it may appear that certain additional features, e.g., decoys or extra radar coverage, would add greatly to capability but not much to cost. Or the cost group may report that certain arctic installations are extremely expensive and that relocating them would reduce costs greatly with little impairment of effectiveness. In both cases the systems have to be modified again. This cut-and-try procedure is essential. Indeed, this process of redesigning the alternatives is probably a more important contribution than the final cost-effectiveness exhibits themselves. In any event, preparing such an analysis is a process of probing and not at all a methodical, scientific comparison following prescribed procedures (Quade 1964, chapter 3).

The incommensurables and uncertainties in cost-benefit analysis are pervasive. Consider the achievement of each of the multiple objectives mentioned above. The various achievements or effects of the alternative systems can perhaps be individually described, but they cannot be expressed in terms of a common denominator. Judgments about the extent of these effects and their worth have to be made. Similarly, some costs—the opportunity cost of devoting resources to defense, the sacrifice of crew lives, the impairment of morale and alertness in the performance of dull, monotonous tasks—if quantifiable at all, cannot validly be put in terms of a common denominator. Furthermore, because of uncertainties, whatever estimates can be prepared should in principle be probability distributions rather than unique figures for costs and gains. The system that performs the best in one contingency may perform the worst in another. This may call for redesigning the systems to insure against catastrophic outcomes, and it definitely calls for caution in interpreting the results of cost-benefit analyses. Finally, costs and gains occur over a period of time, not at a single point in time, and there is no fully acceptable means of handling these streams in analyzing defense options. To be compared, alternative cost-gain streams must each be reduced to a single number, such as present worth. Capabilities occurring in different years can hardly be so discounted satisfactorily. They must therefore be stipulated, and only the cost streams discounted. But when the time path or anything else is stipulated, this implies that there are no trade offs. Also, discounting the cost streams alone poses some problems. For example, most persons would be inclined to discount risky proposals at high rates—but with the gains stipulated, unless risks under alternative systems are carefully equalized, the risky proposals would be relatively cheap and attractive! (For more detail on the difficulties regarding incommensurables, uncertainties, and time, see Hitch & McKean 1960, chapters 10, 11.)

These difficulties are present because life is complex and choice is hard. They are not created by cost-benefit analysis. Moreover, they do not render such quantitative economic analysis useless. They simply mean that the analysts have to be discriminating about when and how to use various tools. Cost-benefit analyses are less helpful in applications where uncertainties are great, as in the case of choosing between disarmament options or between exploratory research and development proposals, and in cases where incommensurables are highly significant, as in selecting the size of defense programs, than they are in choosing between certain force-structure alternatives, such as alternative mixes of Polaris and Minuteman missiles or alternative base locations.

Perhaps the main conclusion, however, is that we must always regard analyses as only aids or inputs to decisions, not as oracular touchstones. (And, needless to say, fragments of cost-benefit analyses, interaction models, games that force people to consider the reactions of allies and enemies, improvements in computational and analytical techniques—any activities that help shed light on costs or gains—are also inputs to decisions and can help increase economic efficiency in defense.) Even the most comprehensive of cost-benefit analyses must be interpreted, not applied mechanically. If employed cautiously and with institutional checks and balances to insure against misuse, cost-benefit analyses can be quite useful. They can sometimes help eliminate really bad choices, allowing the decision makers to choose from a short list of reasonably good options. They can sometimes point with considerable clarity to improvements, even though neither they nor any other technique can identify truly optimal choices. Most important of all, cost-benefit analyses can provide the right framework for decision makers, bargainers, or anyone else “to think in.” It is the right kind of frame-work to use in organizing the evidence and one’s thoughts and intuitions regarding alternatives.

The role of institutional arrangements. In defense, as in other problems of choice, we must recognize that factors other than information and exhortation play a role in shaping actual choices. The hypothesis that each individual, including the official, attempts to maximize his own utility should be kept in mind, and the way in which rules and institutions shape the costs and rewards confronting the individual should be recognized.

The utility-maximization hypothesis does not imply that people are extremely selfish and brutish or anything of the sort. It merely holds that individuals get satisfaction from many things—play, power, material goods, spiritual well-being, helping others, getting their own way—and that these things are to some extent substitutes for each other. That being the case, if the cost to consumers or officials of one item or action increases, they will demand less of it and more of other things. An increase in the rewards to officials or other individuals from one item or action will cause them to demand more of it and less of other items. (For a discussion of the utility-maximization hypothesis, see Alchian & Allen 1964, chapter 2.) This general theorem can lead to many testable hypotheses regarding both private and public activities, including defense.

Models of the private economy make use of this hypothesis, and they yield many good predictions. In the private sector of the economy, the price mechanism causes individuals to feel most of the costs of and gains from their actions. In the public sector the bargaining mechanism, although a very imprecise instrument, performs some of the same function (Lindblom 1955). If a decision maker contemplates an action, he will consider some of the costs he would impose on others, at least on those who have the power to retaliate. He will consider some of the gains he would bestow on others, at least on those with whom he can bargain for favors. Spill-over costs and gains prompt one to consider central intervention as a mechanism to capture these, yet central control can actually so blunt the bargaining mechanism as to lead to the neglect of such externalities. If there are more checks and balances, top management may be impelled to take more of the costs and gains into account. In any organization there is a whole spectrum of possible bargaining arrangements, each with its own advantages and disadvantages.

These points are pertinent to defense planning. A high degree of centralization brings some advantages, but it also means that bargaining power is less dispersed, and so ultimately important considerations may be disregarded (Schlesinger 1966). In a defense department, as in any bureaucracy, there are natural tendencies to centralize authority. With five-year program budgeting, this tendency may be unduly reinforced. Although the defense minister or chief may wish to coordinate interrelated choices, as long as the military branches have the authority to allocate their own budgets they will do much as they please anyway. So the program budget may become, not an information system, but an approved five-year plan that serves as an institutional instrument of control.

This arrangement can correct some of the undesirable effects of the rivalry between military branches in shaping programs that are interrelated. But, as I have argued above, the fact that centralization brings gains does not automatically mean that it is an improvement. For it also brings some ill effects or costs, which should be weighed against the gains. With centralization one set of views plays a greater role in decision making, and dissenting views play lesser roles. In other words, there are fewer checks and balances on the views of the central group. Also, if central managers try to control in much detail, they find it imperative to simplify decision making and to discourage program changes. Finally, lower-level incentives to dissent and criticize and urge changes may diminish if such activities begin to be unrewarding. All these forces can in the long run produce disadvantages: (1) the suppression of alternatives; (2) a neglect of part of the costs and gains from alternative policies; and (3) a neglect of uncertainties.

One group’s view of the future will be less diversified than the separate judgments of a multiplicity of groups. Dominance of one group may lead to the disregarding of trade offs and options that others may take seriously, to the treating of certain costs and gains more lightly than others would, and to the regarding of a particular subset of contingencies and uncertainties as the major ones. The need to simplify—to use half-page summaries and rules of thumb—strengthens these same tendencies. They may be further reinforced by a loss of incentives at lower levels, perhaps by tacit agreements to refrain from introducing disturbing considerations. For some choices, such as force-structure decisions that have crucial interrelationships, central control is appropriate. For other choices, such as exploratory research and development decisions that are dominated by uncertainty, a greater degree of decentralization may be desirable.

We need to learn more about institutional arrangements for harnessing the efforts of individuals to promote various objectives. We have much to learn about the effects on incentive of alternative bargaining structures, procedures, “rules of the game,” relationships between defense agencies and contractors, and so on. In the U.S. Department of Defense and in similar organizations in other nations, numerous institutional modifications are being tried, such as organizational changes, program budgeting, incentive contracts, contracts in which savings resulting from the use of cheaper components are shared, and stock funds under which certain activities are managed almost like private businesses (Hitch & McKean 1960, chapter 12). In the long run, institutional arrangements will turn out to be fully as important as the use of an economic calculus in improving defense choices.

Roland N. Mckean

[See alsoBudgeting; Civil-military relations; Military policy; and the detailed guide under Militarism.]

BIBLIOGRAPHY

Alchian, Armen A.; and Allen, William R. (1964) 1965 University Economics. Belmont, Calif.: Wadsworth.

Davis, Otto A.; and Whinston, Andrew B. 1963 Welfare Economics and the Theory of Second Best. Un-published manuscript. → A paper jointly sponsored by the Cowles Commission for Research in Economics and the Graduate School of Industrial Administration of the Carnegie Institute of Technology.

Devons, Ely 1950 Planning in Practice: Essays in Aircraft Planning in War-time. Cambridge Univ. Press.

Enke, Stephen 1954 Some Economic Aspects of Fissionable Material. Quarterly Journal of Economics 68:217–232.

Enthoven, Alain; and Rowen, Henry 1961 Defense Planning and Organization. Pages 365–417 in Universities-National Bureau Committee for Economic Research, Public Finances: Needs, Sources, and Utilization; A Conference. . . . Princeton Univ. Press.

Harris, Seymour E. 1951 The Economics of Mobilization and Inflation. New York: Norton.

Hirshleifer, Jack 1963 Disaster and Recovery: A Historical Survey. Selected RAND Abstracts, Vol. 1. Research Memorandum RM-3079-PR. Santa Monica, Calif.: RAND Corp.

Hitch, Charles J. 1958 Economics and Military Operations Research. Review of Economics and Statistics 40:199–209.

Hitch, Charles J. 1965 Decision-making for Defense. Berkeley: Univ. of California Press.

Hitch, Charles J.; and McKEAN, ROLAND N. 1960 The Economics of Defense in the Nuclear Age. Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard Univ. Press.

Hoag, Malcolm W. 1959 Some Complexities in Military Planning. World Politics 11:553–576.

Klein, Burton H.; and Meckling, William H. 1958 Application of Operations Research to Development Decisions. Operations Research 6:352–363.

Knorr, Klaus 1956 The War Potential of Nations. Princeton Univ. Press.

Levine. Robert A. 1963 The Arms Debate. Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard Univ. Press.

Lincoln, George A. (1950) 1954 Economics of National Security: Managing America’s Resources for Defense. 2d ed. Englewood, Cliffs, N.J.: Prentice-Hall.

Lindblom, Charles E. 1955 Bargaining: The Hidden Hand in Government. Research Memorandum RM-1434-RC. Santa Monica, Calif.: RAND Corp.

Mckean, Roland N. 1963 Cost-Benefit Analysis and British Defense Expenditure. Pages 17–35 in Alan T. Peacock and D. J. Robertson (editors), Public Expenditure: Appraisal and Control. Edinburgh: Oliver & Boyd.

Marshall, Andrew W.; and Meckling, William H. 1962 Predictability of the Costs, Time and Success of Development. Pages 461–475 in Universities-National Bureau Committee for Economic Research, The Rate and Direction of Inventive Activity: Economic and Social Factors. Princeton Univ. Press.

MassÉ, Pierre 1959 Le choix des investissements: Critères et méthodes. Paris: Dunod.

Nelson, Richard R. 1961 Uncertainty, Learning, and the Economics of Parallel Research and Development Efforts. Review of Economics and Statistics 43:351–364.

Novick, David (editor) 1965 Program Budgeting: Program Analysis and the Federal Budget. Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard Univ. Press.

Peck, Merton J.; and Scherer, Frederic M. 1962 The Weapons Acquisition Process: An Economic Analysis. Boston: Harvard Univ., Graduate School of Business Administration, Division of Research.

Quade, Edward S. (editor) 1964 Analysis for Military Decisions. Chicago: Rand McNally.

Rand Corporation 1958 Report on a Study of Non-military Defense. Santa Monica, Calif.: The Corporation.

Robbins, Lionel 1947 The Economic Problem in Peace and War: Some Reflections on Objectives and Mechanisms. London: Macmillan.

Schelling, Thomas C. 1960 The Strategy of Conflict. Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard Univ. Press.

Scherer, Frederic M. 1964 The Weapons Acquisition Process: Economic Incentives. Boston: Harvard Univ., Graduate School of Business Administration, Division of Research.

Schlesinger, James R. 1960 The Political Economy of National Security: A Study of the Economic Aspects of the Contemporary Power Struggle. New York: Praeger.

Schlesinger, James R. 1963 Quantitative Analysis and National Security. World Politics 15:295–315.

Schlesinger, James R. 1966 Organizational Structure and Planning. Unpublished manuscript, National Bureau of Economic Research (New York).

About this article

Economics of Defense

Updated About encyclopedia.com content Print Article