Proclus

views updated May 29 2018

PROCLUS

(b. Byzantium, 410 [412?]; d. Athens, 485)

Philosophy, mathematics, astronomy.

Proclus’ parents, Patricius and Marcella, were wellborn citizens of Lycia; and his father had attained eminence as an advocate in the courts of Byzantium. Proclus received his early education at the grammar school of Xanthus, a city on the southern coast of Lycia. He was later sent to Alexandria, where he began the study of rhetoric and Latin in preparation for following his father’s career. But on a visit to Byzantium during these years he experienced a “divine call,” as his biographer Marinus tells us (chs. 6, 9, 10), to devote himself to philosophy. Returning to Alexandria, Proclus studied Aristotle with Olympiodorus the Elder and mathematics with a certain Heron, otherwise unknown. But these teachers did not satisfy his; and before he was twenty, he moved to Athens, where the Platonic Academy had recently undergone a notable revival under the headship of Plutarch of Athens. From this until his death in 485 Proclus was a member of the Academy, first as student, then as a teacher, and finally as its head’whence the title Diadochus (Successor) which is usually attached to his name.

Proclus was the last great representative of the Philosophical movement now called Neoplatonism. The first notable exponent of this Hellenistic form of Platonism was Plotinus, from who the doctrine had been transmitted, through Porphyry and Iamblichus, to Plutarch and Syrianus, Proclus’ teachers at Athens. During these two centuries Neoplatonism had taken on a more pronounced religious coloration and had acquired a tincture of the Eastern predilection for magic, or “theurgy,” as Iamblichus called it; on the other hand, its logical structure had become more precise and systematic, and its exponents had turned increasingly to scholarly examination and exposition of the writings of Plato and Aristotle.

Proclus had an extraordinarily acute and orderly mind. Because of his religious temperament he enthusiastically espoused Neoplatonism and devoted his talents and energies to perfecting it by systematizing and extending the views of his predecessors, strengthening their logical structure, and showing in detail their derivation from the teaching of Plato, who was taken as the source and final authority. But Proclus was more than a systematic metaphysician. He had a broad interest in all products of Greek culture, in religion, literature, science, and philosophy. His literary producstion was tremendous. Many of his writings have been lost, but those remaining constitute a priceless source of information regarding this last stage of Greek culture; and because of their underlying philosophy they embody an impressive restatement of Greek rationalism in its last confrontation with Christian thought.

The goal of philosophy, according to the Neoplatonists, was to attain a vision of and contact with the transcendent and ineffable One, the principle from which all things proceed and to which they all, according to their several natures and capacities, endeavor to return. But this synthesizing insight was to be attained only by the hard labor of thought. Proclus believed that a prerequisite to the study of philosophy was a thorough grounding in logic, mathematics, and natural science. One of the most important of his extant writings is the Commentary on the First Book of Euclid’s Elements, in part certainly a product of his lectures at the Academy. Proclus was not a creative mathematician; but he was an acute expositor and critic, with a thorough grasp of mathematical method and a detailed knowledge of the thousand years of Greek mathematics from Thales to his own time. Because of his interest in the principles underlying mathematical thought and their relation to ultimate philosophical principles, Proclus’ commentary is a notable—and also the earliest—contribution to the philosophy of mathematics. Its numerous references to the views of Euclid’s predecessors and successors, many of them otherwise unknown to us, render it an invaluable source for the history of the science.

In the same vein but of more limited interest today is Proclus’ Hypolyposis [Outline] of the Hypotheses of the Astronomers, an elaborate exposition of the system of eccentrics and epicycles assumed in Ptolemy’s astronomy. This Ptolemaic system had arisen out of an effort to provide a mathematical explanation of the anomalies in the motions of the heavenly bodies as observed from the earth. Proclus approved the motives that led to its construction, and thought a knowledge of it desirable for his students; but he was understandably critical of its complexity as a whole and of the ad hoc character of its individual hypotheses. Several other writings on astronomy are attributed to Proclus: an elementary treatise entitled Sphaera, which appeared in more than seventy editions or translations during the early Renaissance; a paraphrase of Ptolemy’s astrological Tetrabihhs; and another astrological essay entitled Eclipses, extant in two different Latin translations. Finally, his Elements of Physics offered a summary of books VI and VII of Aristotle’s Physics and the first book of De caeo, arranged in geometrical form with propositions and proofs.

Proclus’ most systematic philosophical work is his Elements of Theology, which presented in geometrical form, in a series of propositions, each supported by its proof, the successive grades of being that proceed from the superexistent and ineffable One downward to the levels of life and soul. The treatise Platonic Theology, probably a later work, presented this hierarchy of divine principles as they were revealed in Plato’s dialogues, particularly in the Parmenides. Planned on a grandiose scale, this work either was not completed or has been imperfectly transmitted to us.

Better known is the impressive series of commentaries on Platonic dialogues: a lengthy commentary on the Timaeus—;which, Marinus tells US (ch. 38), was Proclus’ favorite—another equally long commentary on the Parmenides, another on the First Alcibiades, and still another on the Republic. The texts of all these have been preserved. His commentary on the Cratylus survives only in fragments, and those on thePhilebus, the Theaetetus, the Sophistand the Phaedo have been completely lost, as have those he is reported to have written on Aristotle. We possess only a fragment of Proclus’ commentary on the Enneads of Plotinus, and we know of his Eighteen Arguments for the Eternity of the World, a tract against the Christians, only because it is extensively quoted in Philoponus’ book written to refute it. His treatises On Providence and Fate and On the Subsistence of Evils were long known only in Latin translations, but large portions of the Greek text have recently been recovered and edited.

Of Proclus’ numerous works on religion, none survives except in fragments. Like Aristotle, he believed that ancient traditions often contain truth expressed in mythical form. Orphic and Chaldean theology engaged his attention from his earliest years in Athens. He studied Syrians’ commentary on the Orphic writings along with the works of Porphyry and Iamblichus on the Chaldean Oracles; and he undertook a commentary of his own on this collection, which, Marinus states (ch. 26), took five years to write. Proclus himself was a devout adherent of the ancient faiths, scrupulously observing the holy days of both the Egyptian and Greek calendars—for, he said, it behooves the philosopher to be the hiero-phant of all mankind, not of one people only (Marinus, ch. 19).

Proclus never married and made liberal use of his apparently ample means for the benefit of his relatives and friends. His diet was abstemious but not ascetic, although he customarily refrained, in Pythagorean fashion, from eating meat. He composed many hymns to the gods, of which seven survive, written in Homeric language and marked by literary quality as well as religious feeling. We are told that he lived in constant communication with the divine world, addressing his adoration and aspiration in prayers and ritual observances and receiving messages from the gods in dreams. His pious biographer also presents him as something of a wonder-worker who, having been initiated into the secrets of the hieratic art, practiced necromancy and other forms of divination and who was able by his arts to produce rain and to heal disease. Such beliefs, like the belief in astrology which both he and Ptolemy held, were almost universal in that age.

Proclus deserves to be remembered, however, not for these beliefs that he shared with almost all his contemporaries, but for the qualities he possessed that are exceedingly rare in any age and were almost unique in his: the logical clarity and firmness of his thought, the acuteness of his analyses, his eagerness to understand and his readiness to present the views of his predecessors on controversial issues, the sustained coherence of his lengthy expositions, and the large horizon, as broad as the whole of being, within which his thinking moved.

Proclus’ thought indirectly exercised considerable influence in the early Middle Ages through the writings of the so-called Dionysius the Areopagite, whose teachings were a thinly disguised version of Proclus’ doctrines. With the revival of learning in the fifteenth century and the desire of Renaissance thinkers to throw off the yoke of medieval Aristotlelianism, Proclus’ Platonism had a great vogue in the Florentine Academy and strongly influenced Nicholas of Cusa and Johannes Kepler. Modern criticism has tended, rather hastily, to discredit his interpretation of Plato; and with the decline of interest in speculative philosophy, his writings have fallen into neglect. But it is fair to say that the wealth of learning and insight in his works does not deserve to be neglected, and that the constructive philosophy they contain still awaits adequate appraisal and appreciation by modern philosophers.

BIBLIOGRAPHY

I. Original Works. Procli philosophi Platonici opera inedita, Victor Cousin, ed., 2nd ed. (Paris, 1864), contains text of Commentary on the Parmenides, French trans. by A. Chaignet, 3 vols. (Paris, 1901–1903).

Separate eds. of other texts are: Commentary on the First Alcibiades of Plato, L. G, Westerink, ed. (Amsterdam, 1959), English trans, by William O’Neill (The Hague, 1965); Commentary on the Timaeus, Ernst Diehl, ed., 3 vols. (Leipzig, 1903–1906), French trans, by A. J. Festugière, 5 vols. (Paris, 1966–1968); Commentary on the Republic, Wilhelm Kroll, ed., 2 vols. (Leipzig, 1899–1901), French trans., by A. J. Festugière, 3 vols. (Paris, 1970); Elements of Physics, Albert Ritzenfeld, cd., with a German trans. (Leipzig, 1911); Hypotyposis, Charles Manitius, ed., with a German trans. (Leipzig, 1909); Commentary on the First Book of Euclid’s Elements, Gottfried Friedlein, ed. (Leipzig, 1873), German trans, by Leander Schönbergcr (Halle, 1945), French trans, by Paul ver Eecke (Bruges, 1949), English trans, by Thomas Taylor, 2 vols. (London, 1792), and Glenn R. Morrow (Princeton, 1970); Commentary on the Cratylus, G. Pasquali, ed. (Leipzig, 1908); Elements of Theology, E. R. Dodds, ed., with an English trans., 2nd ed. (Oxford, 1963); Platonic Theology, H. D. Saffrey and L. G. Westerink, eds., with a French trans. (Paris, 1968), English trans, by Thomas Taylor (London, 1816); Providence and Fate and Subsistence of Evils, Helmut Boese, ed. (Berlin, 1960); and Hymns, E. Vogt, ed. (Wiesbaden, 1957), Thomas Taylor, ed., with an English trans. (London, 1793).

For a complete list of Proclus’ writings, with a bibliography of eds. and translations of individual items during the modern period to 1940, see Rosán (below), 245–254.

II. Secondary Literature. An ancient biography is Vita Procli by his pupil and successor Marinus, J. F. Boissonade, ed. (Leipzig, 1814), repr. in Cousin, Procli … Ptatonici opera inedita. See W. Beierwaltes, Proklos (Frankfurt am Main, 1965); Rudolf Beutler,“Proklos(4)” in Pauly-Wissowa, Real-Encyclopäddie der classischen Altertumwissenchaft, XXIII (1957), 186–247; Raymond Klibansky, “Ein Proklus-fund und seine Bedeutung,” which is Sitzungsberichte der Heidelberger Akademie der Wissenschaften, 19 , no. 5 (1929); Laurence J. Rosán, The Philosophy of Proclus (New York, 1949); A. E. Taylor, “The Philosophy of Proclus” in Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, 18 (1918), 600–635; Friedrich Ueberweg, Grundriss der Geschichte der Philosophic, I, Die Philosophie des Altertums, 12th ed., Karl Praechter, ed. (Berlin, 1926), 621 631; Thomas Whittaker, The Neo-Platonists, 2nd ed. (Cambridge, 1928), 155–184, 231–314; and E. Zeller, Die Philosophie der Griechen, 5th ed., III sec. 2 (Leipzig, 1921), 834–890.

Glenn R. Morrow

Proclus

views updated May 18 2018

PROCLUS

Also generally called Diadochus (successor) because he succeeded to the head of the Platonic Academy at Athens, a pagan Greek Neoplatonist who was hostile to the Catholic Church but who greatly influenced medieval and Renaissance Christian philosophy and theology; b. Byzantium, a.d. 410 or 412; d. Athens, April 17, 485. After his elementary education at Xanthus in Lycia, Proclus went to Alexandria, Egypt, where he studied rhetoric and Roman law, then mathematics and philosophy, the last under Olympiodorus the Peripatetic. Moving to Athens c. 430, he continued his study of philosophy in the Platonic Academy under Plutarch of Athens and, especially, under Syrianus. Shortly after the latter's death, Proclus assumed the leadership of the academy, which he held until his death.

Proclus wrote voluminously on literary, scientific, religious, and philosophical topics. The following are his most important writings still extant in whole or in part. On literature: commentary on Hesiod's Works and Days. On science: commentary on Euclid's Elements, on the introduction to Nicomachus' Arithmetic ; Sphaera, on eclipses, elements of physics. On religion: several hymns, the hieratic art, on the Chaldean philosophy. In philosophy: commentaries on Plato's Parmenides, Timaeus, First Alcibiades, Cratylus, Republic; Eighteen Arguments in Favor of the Eternity of the World Against the Christians; The Platonic Theology; Ten Doubts Concerning Providence; On Providence, Fate and Free Will; On the Existence of Evil; Elements of Theology. Medieval and Renaissance authors were acquainted almost solely with the last four treatises and best of all with the fourth of these.

In Elements of Theology Proclus speaks of many items that may seem to be subsistent and autonomous: limit, infinity, being, eternity, wholeness, life, time. Eventually, though, all these merge with one or other of those hypostases that he clearly intends as somehow independent: the One, the intelligence, the soul, nature. Hence, his universe is made up of four levels, hierarchically arranged: the One (together with multiple "ones" or henads), the intelligence (and intelligences, both divine and merely intellectual), the soul (and souls, both supermundane and intramundane), nature and the sensible world. Proclus' view of this universe is a cosmogony, since at least two sorts of causality are operative in it, both of which are spontaneous and necessary. The one is a process of participation: participations come to be present in participants, which they complete and perfect as integral parts. The other is not: the participations themselves and their participants originate by emanating from the monads (e.g., the intelligence, the soul), which stand at the head of each level of reality and which ultimately arise from the One. Throughout the twofold causality two forces are constantly at work: a procession of everything downward from the One and a reversion of everything back to the One because of desire. Proclus' universe is also a monism since the effect is never totally distinct from the cause. Finally, in his Weltanschauung Proclus owes more to Plato, Iamblichus and Syrianus than to Plotinus; he leans heavily also upon the Orphic hymns and Chaldean oracles.

See Also: platonism; scholasticism, 1.

Bibliography: For a bibliog. of texts and trs. to 1945, see l.j. rosÁn, The Philosophy of Proclus (New York 1949), 245260. Texts. Procli Diadochi Lycii Elementatio physica, ed. h. boese (Berlin 1958); Tria opuscula: De providentia, Libertate, Malo, ed. h. boese (Berlin 1960); Elements of Theology, ed. e. r. dodds (2d ed. Oxford 1963); Commentarium in Parmenidem, ed. r. klibansky and c. labowsky in v. 3 of Plato Latinus (London 1953) 2381; La teologia platonica, ed. e. turolla (Bari 1957); Commentary on the First Alcibiades of Plato, ed. l. g. westerink (Amsterdam 1954). c. vansteenkiste, ed., "Procli Elementatio theologica translata a Guilelmo de Moerbeke," Tijdschrift voor philosophie 13 (1951) 264302, 491531. Studies. l. sweeney, "Origin of Participant and of Participated Perfections in Proclus' Elements of Theology, " in Wisdom in Depth (Milwaukee 1966). j. trouillard, "La Causalité selon Proclus," Revue des sciences religieuses 37 (1958) 347357; "Âme et esprit selon Proclus," Revue des études augustiniennes 5 (1959) 112; "La Monadologie de Proclus," Revue philosophique de Louvain 57 (1959) 309320.

[l. sweeney]

Proclus Diadochus

views updated Jun 08 2018

Proclus Diadochus

Proclus Diadochus (410-485) was a Byzantine philosopher and the last of the great Neoplatonists of antiquity. His philosophy indirectly influenced Christian thought, and he directly influenced many Renaissance thinkers.

Proclus was born in Constantinople (modern Istanbul) of Lycian parentage. He received his elementary education in Xanthus and then continued his studies in Alexandria. Among his teachers were the Sophist Leonas of Isauria and the Egyptian grammarian Orion as well as a number of Roman teachers, who taught him Latin. His basic study was rhetoric, since his intention originally was to enter the legal profession. However, on a trip to Constantinople with Leonas, Proclus appears to have been "converted" to philosophy, and on his return to Alexandria he studied Aristotle and mathematics. At the age of 19 he went to the Platonic Academy in Athens, where he studied under Plutarch of Athens, founder of the Athenian school of Neoplatonism, and Syrianus, Plutarch's immediate successor.

Syrianus greatly influenced Proclus's philosophical development, and he regarded Proclus both as his pupil and as his successor at the Academy. Under Syrianus's tutelage, Proclus read widely in Plato and Aristotle, and at 28 he had produced a number of sophisticated commentaries on different dialogues of Plato, including the monumental commentary on the Timaeus. When Syrianus died, the chair passed briefly to Domninus of Larissa, and it was then assumed by Proclus, who held it until his death.

According to a contemporary biographer, Proclus possessed great bodily strength and endurance and striking physical beauty. He was a practicing magician, a vegetarian, and a man of great personal asceticism. Apart from his professional teaching and writing, he must have at least occasionally spoken his mind on politics, since he left Athens at one time for a year, when political enemies were attempting to put him on trial.

In addition to his commentaries on Plato's dialogues and a commentary on Plotinus's Enneads, Proclus wrote important works on systematic philosophy and theology. They include the Elements of Theology and the Platonic Theology, as well as smaller treatises: Doubts about Providence, Providence and Fate, The Continuance of Evil, and Conduct. He also wrote commentaries on the Chaldean oracles, the first book of Euclid's Elements, and the poets Hesiod and (possibly) Homer, several astronomical treatises, a treatise on the elements of physics, and a large number of hymns to different gods.

Further Reading

As examples of Proclus's work the reader can examine the Thomas Taylor translation of The Commentaries of Proclus on the Timaeus of Plato (1820) or E. R. Dodds's celebrated edition and translation of The Elements of Theology (1933; 2d ed. 1963). A detailed and sympathetic introduction to the life and work of Proclus is Laurence Jay Rosan, The Philosophy of Proclus: The Final Phase of Ancient Thought (1949). See also Thomas Whittaker, The Neo-Platonists: A Study in the History of Hellenism (1901; 4th ed. 1961). □

Proclus

views updated May 29 2018

Proclus (c.410–85). Neoplatonic philosopher. His many works expound a systematization of the form of Neoplatonism derived from Plotinus via Iamblichus and Syrianus. In line with this tradition, he set considerable store by theurgy (‘divine action’), a kind of white magic that exploited the sympathy between elements and processes underlying the unity of the cosmos, to further the ascent of the soul to the One.